Brain Mythologies



Thomas Fuchs, Thiemo Breyer and Christoph Mundt (eds.)Karl Jaspers’ Philosophy and Psychopathology201410.1007/978-1-4614-8878-1_5
© Springer Science+Business Media New York 2014


5. Brain Mythologies


Jaspers’ Critique of Reductionism from a Current Perspective


Thomas Fuchs 


(1)
Psychiatric Department, Centre of Psychosocial Medicine, University of Heidelberg, Voss-Str. 4, 69115 Heidelberg, Germany

 



 

Thomas Fuchs



Abstract

Karl Jaspers is considered the founder of psychopathology as a science with its own object and own methodology. This foundation was built substantially on his rebuttal of naturalistic reductionism, which is an attempt to reduce mental phenomena and instances of mental illness to the brain’s organic substrate. Psychopathology as a science is based, by contrast, on the assumption that mental abnormalities bear a meaningful and gestalt-like character and thus cannot be exhausted by listing symptoms, which would then be understood as direct reflections of neurobiological disturbances. In his critique of the “Brain Mythologies” in his day, Jaspers opposes overhasty localization of mental functions to certain centers of the brain as well as absolutization of causal research. He contrasts this reductionist approach with an understanding-based approach, established through reenactment, empathy, and thereby the internal relatedness that the therapist feels towards his patient as a fellow human being. The relevance of the Jaspersian critique will be established in view of the current neurobiological paradigm in psychiatry. At the same time, it will be asserted that psychopathology today has become insufficient by being restricted solely to the domain of conscious subjectivity. Only if psychopathology surpasses the subjectivism of understanding and considers biological processes as such to be socially and historically constituted, will it be able to regain its relevance.


Keywords
ReductionismPsychopathologyMethodologyPhenomenologyNeuroscience


Translated by Alexander T. Englert from Fuchs (2008).



5.1 Introduction


Karl Jaspers is considered the uncontested founder of psychopathology as a science with its own object and methodology.1 This establishment of psychopathology was based essentially on the rejection of natural scientific reductionism , which attempted to trace back mental phenomena and occurrences of mental disorders to their source in the organic substrate (i.e., in the brain). Indeed, this reductionism corresponds to the scientific longing for explanations, but it prioritizes the question of why over the question of what and thus neglects the careful describing and understanding of pathological variations of psychic life. Psychopathology as a science by contrast is based for Jaspers on the assumption that even mental abnormalities have gestalt-like and meaningful characteristics and therefore cannot be explained exhaustively by the listing of symptoms, which would be considered reflections of neurobiological disturbances. In contrast to neurology, which correlates single deficiencies with localized physical lesions, psychopathology begins there where both the holistic structure of the mental and, as a result, the constitution of experiencing world and self as a whole suffers from a disturbance. This modified or disturbed constitution cannot be described any longer by reference to individual symptoms, but rather requires a phenomenological presentation of the whole structure of the experienced world. Only if this task is accomplished and the mental illness is understood as a modification of the world-constitution can the search commence for disturbances’ causes, whether they are of a physical, a life-historical, or other sort—namely, by working out from a methodologically secured foundation.

Psychopathology in the 19th Century, by which Jaspers felt confronted, was marked by a dispute between those advocating a “psychic approach” (“Psychiker”) and those advocating a “somatic approach” (“Somatiker”) . The former, above all J. C. A. Heinroth and K. Ideler, sought the causes of mental illnesses in an “aberration” (“Verirrung”) of the psyche itself; often this aberration was interpreted according to moral or even religious perspectives. The latter, on the other hand, amongst them M. Jacobi, F. Nasse, and J. B. Friedreich, denied the possibility that the psyche or the mind itself could fall ill, and they attributed mental illness to physical effects.2 Thus, both schools of thought failed to conceive of the state of being mentally ill in direct accordance with its own structures—namely, through trying to realize the patient’s experience or behavior. Instead, they viewed it solely as a symptom of mental or somatic causes. By doing so, both groups overlooked equally the phenomenological dimension.

Already in the introduction to General Psychopathology,3 Jaspers takes a stance against the “somatic approach” of his time, namely, against reducing everything to the brain’s physiology: “The principle of this book is to present a psychopathology which, in its concept-building, its methods of investigation and general outlook, is not enslaved to neurology and medicine on the dogmatic grounds that ‘psychic disorder is cerebral disorder’” (GP, p. 4). This dogma, which Wilhelm Griesinger (1861) formulated in 1861, leads psychiatrists to the conclusion that, “if only we had an exact knowledge of the brain, we would then know the psychic life and its disturbances. This has led psychiatrists to abandon psychopathological studies as unscientific” (GP, p. 459). All validity is attributed “solely to cerebral processes, constitution, physiology and the experiments of objective psychology since these [are] purely physiological, and as far as possible excluded from psychic life” (GP, p. 712).

At the same time, Jaspers’ critique developed just as severe a criticism of the “psychic approach,” namely, of Freudian psychoanalysis in which he perceived a speculative, ideological tendency at work, which went in the direction of unmasking conscious mental experiences as illusions and self-deceptions (cf. GP, pp. 537 ff., 772 ff.). Albeit misjudging the hermeneutic dimension of psychoanalysis and overlooking the possibilities of extended understanding opened up by it, his critique arose from the same impulse, namely, to assert psychopathology and the primary experiencing of the mentally ill as an independent field of phenomenological knowledge. It also arose from the impulse to defend this field against biological as well as psychological reductionism : “We confine description solely to the things that are present to the patients’ consciousness,” in that we “are not concerned at this stage with (…) any subsidiary speculations, fundamental theory or basic postulates” (GP, p. 56). “The psychopathologist, if he is to keep this space free and gain ground for his activities, must set his face against every attempt to create an absolute and to claim that particular methods of research are the only valid, single objectivities, the only true Being as such. He must also take sides on behalf of meaningful understanding in the face of biologism, mechanism, and technics” (GP, p. 770). In Husserl’s sense of “To the things themselves!”, Jaspers asserts that psychopathology must “withdraw” from the secondary, theoretical world of a purportedly recognized true Being and return “to fully present reality” (GP, p. 549).

In accordance with the dominant psychiatric paradigms of his time, Jaspers’ main critique was aimed at biological reductionism. In the following, this confrontation will be examined in more depth; then, its actuality for contemporary psychiatry and neuroscience will be explored.


5.2 Jaspers’ Critique of Biological Reductionism



5.2.1 The “Somatic Bias”


At the end of the 19th Century, psychiatry conformed to the natural scientific paradigm that had reigned triumphant in the whole field of medicine since 1850. It concentrated on the search for somatic causes of mental illnesses. To do so, research was promoted above all in the areas of neuroanatomy, neurohistology, neurophysiology, and neuropathology.4 Most importantly, one believed it possible to have an effect on mental disturbances via somatic therapies. The majority of psychiatrists considered the psyche and psychology as things that had been supplanted by physiology. In fact, T. Meynert, one of Griesinger’s pupils, rejected the expression of “mental illnesses” completely and spoke from then on only of a “clinic for illnesses of the forebrain” (Meynert 1884).

Around 1900, however, the preliminary euphoria of the somatic approach began to waver. Many results, which were being enthusiastically awaited, had failed to appear; the discovery of lues as the cause for progressive paralysis could not be adopted for other psychoses. The somatic paradigm neither offered a satisfactory explanation for the majority of mental disturbances nor provided effective forms of treatment. Amongst psychiatrists, Jaspers reminisced later that “consciousness of a stagnation in scientific research” was spreading along with pessimism about therapeutic methods.5 Jaspers found himself confronted with this situation as he began working on his new system for psychopathology in Heidelberg.

In the introduction of GP, Jaspers refers to the “somatic bias” as threatening psychiatry. This bias presupposes implicitly, that “the actual reality of human existence is a somatic event. Man is only comprehensible when he is understood in somatic terms; should the psyche be mentioned, this is in the nature of a theoretical stop-gap of no real scientific value” (GP, p. 18). This attitude leads to an overhasty identification of morphological or physiological facts with mental experiences and, in the process, arrives at adventurous constructs, which Jaspers refers to as “Brain Mythologies ” (GP, p. 18). Natural scientific facts are then offhandedly reformulated into statements about “the psyche,” “the person,” or “mental illnesses”—an improper stretching of the physical world’s domain of validity. This somatic-pathological perspective overlooks, according to Jaspers, the independence of the mental domain, which reveals itself solely through a humanities-oriented understanding . “Somatic medicine,” he writes at one point, “only deals with the individual as a creature of nature. It examines and investigates his body as it would that of an animal. But psychopathology is constantly faced with the fact that the individual is a creature of culture” (GP, p. 709). Animals can indeed suffer from brain afflictions and nervous disorders, but mental illnesses are specifically human: “Medicine is only one of the roots of psychopathology (…) Whenever the object studied is Man and not man as a species of animal, we find that psychopathology comes to be not only a kind of biology but also one of the Humanities” (GP, pp. 35/36).

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Apr 6, 2017 | Posted by in PSYCHOLOGY | Comments Off on Brain Mythologies

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access