Informed Consent and Medicolegal Aspects of Neurosurgery




The theory of informed consent has its origins in a multitude of dimensions ranging from law, medical practice, ethics, political policies, social sciences, philosophy, and behavioral sciences. It cannot be viewed purely from the perspective of law or from that of medical science. To understand the doctrine, one needs to understand this multifaceted dimension of informed consent. Throughout history, it has been viewed as rather unethical to inform the patient about the risks involved in the treatment process. Today the medical science has far advanced beyond its own fears, and disclosures of the risks involved in the treatment process have become the norm. Informed consent refers to a set of legal principles that has been set up to define the physician-patient interaction occurring in clinical treatment scenarios. It is a theory based on ethical principles but given effect by legal rulings and put into practice by clinicians. Informed consent is a process of active shared decision-making based on mutual respect and participation and not a ritual of reciting from a piece of paper the possible complications of the intended treatment. Hence, in its essence, informed consent is an ethical principle.


Moral reasoning dictates that an action that leads to well-being is the right action. Beneficence is the core value on which medical practice is based. In beneficence, medical therapy aims at treating patients in ways that are likely to be beneficial to them. Autonomous action is an action that is self-propagated and legislated. Autonomy is a fundamental human right. Beneficence and autonomy are the two sides of the doctrine of informed consent. Beneficence may not always uphold the principles of autonomy (i.e., a conflict between free choice and the patient’s best interests). Autonomous action ceases to be autonomous when the person involved lacks the necessary cognition, or when the volition is impaired. It is in this context that the concept of therapeutic privilege must be understood. Therapeutic privilege is the situation where the physician may at his or her discretion withhold information from the patient for the reason that disclosing certain information may likely result in serious physical or psychological harm and be detrimental to the patient’s recovery; thereby the physician may be excused from divulging the information. The information that can be withheld may be related to either the diagnosis or the treatment. Such therapeutic nondisclosure is especially important in a patient where psychiatric illness is diagnosed. Therapeutic privilege can be a defense against negligence to take informed consent only when the risks of full disclosure exceeds the risks of treatment. Paternalistic deception is a deception that is deliberately performed for the individual’s own good. Patients may make an informed choice that may actually be medically improper. Paternalism may curb autonomy but may not always be wrong if it might result in the patient’s well-being. The concept of paternalism does not imply that the action is justifiable or unjustifiable but rather that it is an act of beneficence similar to parental beneficence. Paternalism can be weak or strong. The philosophical debate between the paternalism and antipaternalism faces off with the new age concept of autonomy. For the patient to give informed consent, he should be competent enough to understand and make a decision, should receive adequate disclosure of the relevant information, and should make the decision voluntarily.


The History of Informed Consent


To understand the present-day theory of informed consent, it is important to understand the evolution of the theory of informed consent from the historical perspective. The historical incidents where physicians have been subjected to compensation, either in physical or financial form, are not rare. Four thousand years ago, medical malpractice was recognized and was punishable as a crime. The sixth Babylonian king, Hammurabi (1792–1750 bc ), who lived in modern-day Iraq and eastern Syria, is best known for his testimony of legal codes, engraved on a 2.25-meter-high diorite stone stela that is on exhibit at the Louvre in Paris. The code has 282 laws pertaining to various civil and criminal matters with a description of their punishments. Code 218 says, “If a physician operate on a man for a severe wound with a bronze lancet and cause the man’s death, or open an abscess in the eye of a man with a bronze lancet and destroy the man’s eye, they shall cut off his hands” (Code No. 218 of Hammurabi). Although the punishment of cutting the fingers of erring physicians is not comparable to present-day medical malpractice, the financial payment does have resemblance to modern-day medical litigation settlements. Codes 219 and 220 say that “if a physician makes a wound and cures a freeman, he shall receive ten pieces of silver, but only five if the patient is the son of a plebeian or two if he is a slave.” Sushruta Samhita , a treatise on surgery from India written in the 3rd century BC, describes the need for obtaining the consent of the king in certain treatment scenarios like, “If surgical intervention is not done then the patient will die and after surgery it is not certain if surgery will be beneficial.”


In ancient Greece, the patient’s participation in decision-making on medical treatment was considered undesirable. It was thought that any discussion regarding the possible complications would decrease the patient’s trust and confidence in the treatment. In the era of enlightenment, the medical community still felt that “deception” was required to facilitate the treatment. There were dichotomous views as to whether to disclose the prognosis to the patient or to hide it. To effect a treatment cure, it was widely felt that authority must be coupled with obedience. The doctrine of assault versus battery evolved in early English common law. Gradually informed consent has emerged to be more patient oriented, and it has been established that a well-informed patient is a master of his or her own body. Since the 1930s, the courts have largely moved away from the battery theory of informed consent and have adopted the concept of negligence in its place. The negligence theory puts more emphasis on professional standards and expertise than the battery concept. During the 20th century, the courts extended the English common law tort doctrine of negligence to the field of surgery by equating negligence with breach of duty, and breach of duty with incomplete patient consent. The present concept of informed consent has evolved with several landmark judgements in the last century. It is essential that these cases be analyzed to understand the evolution of the present-day theory of informed consent. The first recorded case of medical litigation was Stratton vs. Swanlond in 1374. The case pertained to a surgery on the hand of a patient, which was injured in trauma. The surgery did not result in eradicating the problem. The patient contended that the promised cure was not achieved. The judge held that the physician could be held responsible if harm came to the patient as a result of surgery, and that he could not be held responsible if the intended cure was not achieved despite his best efforts.


In the aftermath of World War II, several trials were held against Nazi Party members for war crimes, under the orders of President Harry Truman. The trials began on December 9, 1946, in Nuremberg, Germany, and came to be known as the Nuremberg trials. One of the trials, the so-called “doctors trial” focused on the inhuman medical experiments that were carried out by the Nazi physicians. The trial promulgated six ethical principles of medical experiments, which later came to be known as the Nuremberg Code. The first principle of the code states the absolute need for voluntary consent in medical experiments. The Nuremberg Code has not been officially accepted as a law by any nation or medical association, but it has formed the basis of many guidelines worldwide.


There are well-known cases involving neurosurgery that have shaped the legal doctrine of informed consent in the United States. The case of Canterbury vs. Spence is a landmark case that defined many issues of informed consent in present-day practice. Jerry Watson Canterbury was an FBI clerk who developed a prolapsed intervertebral disc in 1958 at the age of 19 years. He consulted a well-known neurosurgeon, Dr. William Spence. He was diagnosed to have a prolapsed disc at the T4 level as confirmed by a myelogram. Spence recommended that the patient have a laminectomy. After the surgery, Canterbury had a fall from his bed while still being hospitalized and developed paralysis from the waist down with urinary incontinence. Canterbury underwent a second operation due to the neurologic deterioration. He made some recovery in his motor function but continued to have issues with urinary incontinence. The court held that Spence was negligent in obtaining complete consent. On March 15, 2017, Canterbury passed away, and an obituary was posted in The New York Times about him. This case was a landmark case in the medicolegal context. Before this judgement, the onus of soliciting information about treatment resided with the patient. Describing the risks involved in the proposed treatment was at the doctor’s discretion. He was held negligent only when the treatment was carried out against the wishes of the patient. The 1972 ruling in this case made it mandatory for the doctor to disclose all pertinent information relating to the risks of treatment, and to inform the patient of any alternative forms of treatment available. According to professor Alan Meisel, “The opinion is the cornerstone of the law of informed consent not only in the United States, but in other English-speaking countries, too.” The case shifted the perceptions from “professional practice standard” to a “reasonable person standard.” The Johnson vs. Kokemoor case has opened a new dimension to informed consent. Donna Johnson was diagnosed during an evaluation of her headaches to have a basilar aneurysm. She consulted Dr. Richard Kokemoor, who advised surgery for the aneurysm. Kokemoor informed the patient that he had performed the procedure “dozens of times” and compared the risks involved with those of a tonsillectomy or gallbladder surgery. Kokemoor estimated the risk of death due to surgery at 2%, when in fact it was close to 30% when performed by inexperienced surgeons. Johnson underwent the surgical procedure but developed quadriparesis, incontinence with speech, vision problems, and swallowing disturbances. Johnson filed a suit against Kokemoor, and the jury deliberated in favor of Johnson. The court held that the actual risks involved in the surgery were not conveyed to the patient. Kokemoor had not disclosed the difference in results between experienced and inexperienced surgeons, and he had not disclosed that the mortality rate in the hands of inexperienced surgeons was much higher than what had been disclosed to the patient. It was brought to evidence that Kokemoor had performed the aneurysm clipping in six patients after his residency and had operated on a basilar aneurysm only twice. The plaintiff contested that the doctor should have referred her to a more experienced tertiary care center like Mayo Clinic, which was only 90 miles away. The court held that the defendant failed to do the following: divulge the extent of his experience in performing the specific operation, compare the mortality and morbidity between experienced and inexperienced surgeons, and refer the plaintiff to a more experienced treatment center. The Wisconsin Supreme Court stated that “physicians must provide comparative risk in statistical terms to obtain informed consent.”

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Jun 29, 2019 | Posted by in NEUROSURGERY | Comments Off on Informed Consent and Medicolegal Aspects of Neurosurgery

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access