Neuroethics




© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2014
Ahmed Ammar and Mark Bernstein (eds.)Neurosurgical Ethics in Practice: Value-based Medicine10.1007/978-3-642-54980-9_18


18. Neuroethics



Adefolarin O. Malomo1, 2   and Mark Bernstein 


(1)
Departments of Surgery and Human Anatomy, University of Ibadan, Ibadan, Nigeria

(2)
Department of Neurological Surgery, University College Hospital, Ibadan, Nigeria

(3)
Division of Neurosurgery, Toronto Western Hospital, University of Toronto, 399 Bathurst Street, Toronto, ON, M5T 2S8, Canada

 



 

Adefolarin O. Malomo



 

Mark Bernstein (Corresponding author)




18.1 Introduction


The actual and potential applications of neuroscience are so profound in human self-understanding, that the exploration of their ethical implications is a major concern and justification of the relatively new bioethical field called neuroethics (Farah 2010; Illes and Sahakian 2011). The practice of neuroethics focuses on the ethics of neuroscience (Racine and Illes 2008). It concerns the ethical, legal, and social impact of the neurosciences, including ways in which neurotechnology can or could be used to predict or alter human behavior (Roskies 2002). Neuroethics has been defined as “the ethics of neuroscience and the neuroscience of ethics” (Roskies 2002), but clearly the former constitutes the major and important part of neuroethics. With rapid advances in our technological ability to investigate and alter brain function, this field will gain more relevance and importance in the future (Lipsman and Bernstein 2009, 2011) for all neurosurgeons and especially functional neurosurgeons. Value-based medicine can help inform neuroethics debates.


18.2 Illustrative Case (Seeking Information About Contracting a Degenerative Brain Disease)


John Curious is a 59 year old Associate Professor of African Literature born of a British mother and an African father. He lives in the United States of America. His mother suffered from severe depression and later died of disseminated malignancy at the age of 69. His elder brother has suffered from epilepsy of unknown cause since he was 30 years old. His father succumbed from dementia, probably of Alzheimer type. John has followed developments in the neurosciences in the media and he recently saw advertisements for noninvasive brain scans like fMRI and genetic tests which might help define his neurological genetic, structural, and functional status. He decides to get the tests and awaits the results with guarded anticipation. What are the ethical implications of this situation?


18.3 Approach to the Case


Respecting John’s autonomy would clearly suggest that it is his right to undertake whatever tests he wishes and to seek whatever information about himself he wishes to, as long as the risk/benefit ratio of the tests is acceptable. Against this is the potential societal harm if everyone knew about various conditions he/she might have or have the potential to develop. This knowledge could lead to the consumption of limited health-care resources needed by people with actual diseases and thus pose a threat to justice and an ethical challenge in the realm of priority setting (resource allocation). And what if the test reveals something unexpected and devastating like an existing glioblastoma multiforme or a predisposition to develop one? What would be the duty of disclosure and by whom? What about the reliability of the tests – has there been sufficient preclinical data to demonstrate sufficient accuracy of the results? At the bottom line, is society ready for its citizens to have access to finding out information about themselves that was just not meant to be found in this way or that society at large is not prepared to handle?


Pearl

Neuroethics is a fairly new subdivision of bioethics focusing mainly on the ethical issues raised by advances in the neurosciences. To date its main areas of application are the ethical uses of fMRI, pharmacological enhancement, and “psychosurgery.”


18.4 Discussion



18.4.1 Neuroethics of Enhancement


By enhancement is meant adding to what is normally considered adequate or normal. Medical norms are usually statistically derived from a population of those considered healthy. Can we, however, derive “ought” from “is” in medicine? The validity of this empirical “is” and empirical “ought” is confirmed by the balance, harmony, and homeostasis maintained, but do we know that the present balance and homeostasis are the only possible homeostasis complex possible or are they relative? We cannot be sure. Many average parameters in many societies have altered without any ill effects; however, other changes have been attended with disequilibrium, and so the need for caution remains.

Human history is full of examples of technological advancements being greeted with horror, going through acceptance to desire and high demand. Also, devices and methods that are developed for one purpose become adapted and improved to cater to a wider range of challenges (Arras et al. 1999). In all of these, world views, goals, and values seem to be elastic in ultimately adjusting to the new scopes of reality and possibility. History has also shown that more is not always better.


18.4.1.1 Pharmacological Enhancement


Examples of relevant neuropharmacological agents used for enhancement include selective serotonin reuptake inhibitors (SSRI) that can make nondepressed persons feel even better with side effects that can be mitigated by yet other drugs, methylphenidate and amphetamines that can increase attention focus and sustenance in persons without attention-deficit hyperactive disorder (ADHD), ampakines that can further improve normal memory, modafinil that can increase wakefulness in persons without narcolepsy, and sildenafil that improves sexual performance in some normal males (Farah 2002).

Issues of ethics abound in all these uses. Chemically altering and then readjusting our internal environment has biological implications in the long run. Functional costs sometimes exist, as in the case of memory expanders that tend to reduce capacity for generalization in reasoning. On the other side, it may be paternalistic to disallow adults to choose for themselves. Also temporary enhancement may be required in unusual circumstances such as combat situations. What must be advocated, however, is that proper cost-benefit analyses be undertaken before those saddled with the responsibilities present these as options to potential users especially for enhancement purposes. Society should also be educated to know that medicine as a whole and psychiatry in particular are imprecise sciences. In psychiatry, mind parameters are dynamic with the environment and advertisements and other social pressures are some of the relevant factors in self, need, and mood perceptions.

In many countries, enhancement medicines are now consumerism driven, yet drugs that have been so offered are sometimes found dangerous years later. Examples include SSRI that are now regarded as dangerous decades later and benzodiazepines which now have problems of epidemic iatrogenic addiction. Often, somehow, some of these challenges become well known only after drug patents have expired (Pieters and Snelders 2009). Obviously increased stringency in the conditions of making enhancement drugs available and education to make the public more wary are important responsibilities of all concerned.

At social levels, it can be argued that wariness over the advantages of these forms of enhancement is inconsistent with the usual practice of other ways of enhancing opportunities, for instance, by getting the best school possible for children and a regular workout regime that builds one’s body. These methods that enhance through natural mechanisms can usually be differentiated from those that are imposed by the use of chemicals or technology from without because unlike the latter, the former are harmonious and enduring forms of gain in the body.

Would enhancement not make the strong relatively stronger and the weak relatively weaker in society? It likely would but that in itself would not be unethical unless it gets to a point when socially desirable goals are missed demonstrably because of it or socially undesirable states occur because of it. Normally, enhancement is a product of affluence (Elliott 2004). The wealthy also should not be punished just for being so; wealth may have a price which the poor are “unwilling” (Granat 2003) or unable to pay. In any case these social issues raise ethical issues mostly when advantages taken are undue, the process or outcome of enhancement endangers others, or resource allocation is unacceptably skewed.


18.4.1.2 Surgical Enhancement and Psychosurgery


One of the most relevant applications of neuroethics in the world of the neurosurgeon relates to the growing specialty of altering abnormal and normal states with the use of psychosurgery or deep brain surgery. The advent of deep brain stimulation (an impermanent treatment), as opposed to lesion making (a permanent treatment), has made it easier for surgeons to recommend and patients to accept surgical treatment that alters neurophysical and psychological functions. Society is still appropriately mindful of functional neurosurgery and its abuses decades ago (Freeman 1958). The question we all must ask is: Is society ready for increasingly sophisticated interventions which may soon be able to alter normal functions or alter states of mind? Recent qualitative research has shed some light on this issue. A number of studies have shown that both patients and surgeons will accept deep brain surgery for pathological states such as depression or eating disorders, but find ethically dubious its use for enhancement of normal states (Mendelshon et al. 2010, 2013 Lipsman et al. 2011). In another study, patients were willing to accept treatments that may alter identity if it was the only response to threat to life, but they considered procedures to alter a normal state as ethically dubious (Lipsman et al. 2009). All these ethical issues are compounded by additional challenges like informed consent, which in this setting will often be required to be obtained from patients who are cognitively and/or psychiatrically compromised (Grant et al. 2013; Lipsman et al. 2010). Such professional and scientific investigation will go a long way in reassuring society that due diligence is being done to ensure that mistakes of the past are not repeated.

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Mar 11, 2017 | Posted by in NEUROSURGERY | Comments Off on Neuroethics

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access